Ad Verecundiam

"I am right because I say so or because X says so."

The argument from authority is the weakest form of argument, according to Boethius. -- St. Thomas Aquinas


An argumentum ad verecundiam is an argument based on authority. The Latin means "appeal to reverence".

(Here, authorities mean people presumed to be experts, as opposed to people holding power over others--Scott Johnson)

Note that quoting scientific papers (in particular, ones that have survived peer review and other forms of professional scrutiny from the scientific community) is not Ad Verecundiam. Repeating conjectures that are offered by scientists or other authorities when the conjecture is not supported by formal study, is Ad Verecundiam. (See below).

Example: "UFOs are not real, because the great Carl Sagan said so."

It's not so much because of the peer review of the paper, but because it is supposed that the paper documents the actual observations and evidence, i.e. it contains its own propositions that the petitioner and respondent of an argument may agree upon as true (and if they don't, it may be outside the scope of logic to determine the truth). One must appeal to the content of the paper to present a valid argument, not to the fact that it's peer-reviewed. // Had I bothered to read a little more, I would have noticed that this point was already made :p

Fallacious because:

Reverence is an appeal to emotion, intended to cloud one's judgment of the remaining argument.

(Following would seem to be arguments against Ad Autoritatem...)

Experts are often wrong. Perhaps less so than laypersons, but still so.

X may be a statement of opinion rather than fact; in many fields of study "expert opinion" (unsupported by empirical evidence) is considered conjecture and nothing more.

The expert community may be biased. Many a box-office hit has been rubbished by movie critics, for example. And the proletarian community may be naive; many a box-office hit has been rubbish.

X may not be agreed upon by all experts in the community; in many cases X is rejected by a minority of experts (but a minority of experts, or even only one, agree with X). Much quackery seems to fall into this category.

If a particular expert is named ("according to Dr. Sam Snakeoil..."), his expertese may be suspect. (Is this different from "experts may not agree" ? I find quoting a particular source more convincing than quoting a vague "experts say..." or "scientists say...".)

A world-famous expert in one field knows just as little as the average person in most other fields outside his area of expertise.

This is not so clear. Many academics/intellectuals know more that the average person about a lot of subjects beyond there area of expertise, because they tend to get interested in things and spend the time --- moreso that average. The also tend to be more intelligent and better educated than average, which can make gaining such knowledge much more efficient. The fallacy is not in thinking that random expert might have a good opinion on Y, even though she is an expert in X, it is that thinking that her expertise in X is transferrable (of course it isn't).

Experts are often mis-quoted, their statements taken out of context.

A preference may simply be subjective, but the expert does not realize that other minds might not work the same as his/her own.

Sometimes correct, because:

X may be in fact proven; or sufficiently well-demonstrated that it is near-universally regarded as fact.

(Then you point to the study)

Agreed. One issue to remember, though, is many people confuse quoting a study with quoting its authors, and thus quoting a study or paper is dismissed as Ad Verecundiam. A further complication is that a given authority may have published reams of studies on a topic; referring to the person is a common shorthand for referring to his/her body of work (or the subset thereof which is sound scientific argument rather than mere conjecture). When that happens, it's a common fallacy to scream "Ad Verecundiam". // Actually, outright refuting an argument, or more specifically, stating that the conclusion is not true, based on the existence of a logically fallacy in the argument is _itself_ a fallacy, known as Ad Logicam. It's somewhat related to Modus Ponens: the conclusion of a sound argument is irrefutably true (otherwise it's not sound), but nothing can be known of the truth of the conclusion of an unsound argument. // Ahem -- you have conflated two completely different things. Noting a logical fallacy in an argument most certainly does "outright refute" the argument -- that's what refutation of arguments is all about. That it doesn't follow from the invalidity of an argument that its conclusion is false is a different matter altogether. And it is utterly false that nothing can be known of the truth of the conclusion of an unsound argument -- e.g., we know that the conclusion of an unsound argument that 1 = 2 is in fact false. So you have thoroughly mixed up what an argument does or does not demonstrate with what is or is not true.

Expert community may in fact agree that X is true. However, appealing to authority may be a good Heuristic Rule.

I like the distinction that experts' words have no more weight than anyone else's, but they are useful because they can provide information or answers or arguments _and_ the reasons, background and whatever else are required to back it up. Or at the very least references to sources that do.

If expert's words have no more weight than anyone else's, then how can appealing to authority be a good heuristic? Well, because the claim that expert's words have no more weight than anyone else's is fallacious. While an expert may be wrong, it is a false inference to conclude that an expert is just as likely to be wrong as as anyone else. There's a lot of talk here on this Wiki (and elsewhere) about what is or is not fallacious, without any reasoning to back up the talk, without discussion of what it actually means to be fallacious. So one could take this whole article as an example of Ad Verecundiam -- the article poses as and is taken by many as authoritative, when in fact it is full of specious reasoning. A primary problem is that the article author confuses arguments from reverence with arguments from authority; the former are generally fallacious while the latter are only occasionally fallacious.


In circumstances when neither participant is an expert in the field, an Argument From Authority can have value. Examples:

Grandpa: "I've just been bitten by a snake - I think I'd better soak in cold water"

Grandma: "No, my folks always said that you should put vinegar on it, what do you think Mary?"

Mary: "Well, that TV doctor said you should go straight to hospital - I guess he knows best"

This is a case of low-rankers versus low-rankers. All else being equal, it makes sense to take the opinion of somebody who is paid to work in a given field over an amateur. It's the "least evil" choice of authority-versus-authority. We are choosing between two authorities, not between authoritative and non-authoritative evidence. Related: Evidence Totem Pole.

Or:

Student Programmer Bill: "I'm writing my solution in one big module - it will save opening and closing all the files"

Student Programmer Jane: "The professor said we should use separate modules for similar functionality. I can't see that it makes much difference, but I guess we should do as he says"

This line of reasoning is itself fallacious - it's an Appeal To Tradition. For example, it might be that the local hospital is so crowded the emergency room takes 12 hours to treat anyone, in which time Grandpa will die. And it might be that sticking the solution in one big module leads Bill to do away with the filesystem as a program modularization mechanism, and use a soup or an inspector or a diagram to navigate from class to class.

This is a prime example of the Anything Is Possible fallacy. It might be that aliens built the pyramids, or that God created the world 6,000 years ago with all the evidence in place ot make it appear much older. "It might be" statements are as contentful as line noise.

What these folks could have argued logically was:

These are empirical assertions coupled with Hasty Generalization; there's nothing "logical" about it.

Mary: "That hospital is underfunded and understaffed, and Eb Johnson died in their waiting room last week. Let's tourniquet that bite and use the vinegar if Grandma feels sure about it, then try the hospital."

It ought to be mentioned that use of tourniquets for snakebites is a bad idea. The venom will have spread out of the bitten limb, into the body, before any tourniquet can be applied. Instead of someone poisoned by a snakebite, a tourniquet gets you someone poisoned by a snakebite who is also likely to lose a limb even if he/she survives the bite.

Jane: "I'm trying to remember the professor's argument. Oh yes, he said that sticking all the functions in one module would make it difficult to find individual ones and maintain them. Does that make sense to you? Maybe we can find another way to do it!"

Yes, *if* Mary and Jane knew a little something about the subject, they *could* have made these logical arguments. However, in situations where no one knows enough about the subject to make a logical argument, Argument From Authority is a reasonable Heuristic Rule for choosing what to do. One hopes that, while doing that, one will gain enough experience to make a logical argument.

It's sad that so many here subscribe to the logicist fallacy. In fact we invariably make arguments from authority every time we refer to anything we have read or learned but not personally witnessed or deductively proven, and our advance as a civilization is based on that. Arguments from authority are not generally fallacious -- the claim that they are is itself fallacious.

*Bzzt!* Arguments from authority are eo ipso fallacious, but their conclusions are not - and, indeed, are more often correct than not. We make arguments from authority when we refer to what we've read or learned, yes, and that's exactly why it's mentioned above as a good Heuristic Rule.


When refuting Ad Verecundiam it is easy to fall into Ad Hominem.


Ad Verecundiam works great if you reference just the right book author. If, however, you reference one that causes a negative emotional reaction in your target, then even if your case had merit you are screwed. --Phl Ip


There's also a kind of argument from authority in reverse, as in "Oh, that must be false, because that's what says!"

Yeah. "Positive thinking can't cure you, because that's just what Uri Geller says!" I like it. Especially because it's not accurate. UG sez his positive thinking will cure you. --Phl Ip


We apply our personal veracity tests on both quoted authority and presented logic. Of course experts know what they are talking about. It is just very difficult to pick the true expert. And true experts have a 'use by' date - just ask Isaac Newton.

The danger is when the listener has little knowledge of the subject, and her first encounters are all not as expert as she assumed. It is very difficult to change ideas which are accepted as expert. When I look back on the meaning of words used in Information Technology, and I remember what they meant early on, they are invariably reduced in meaning from the original. Two such words come to mind Relational and User Friendly, but there are many.

Relational, at first, meant something quite abstract and useful - Dr Codd's rules covered it. But now Relational means 3NF+ and implemented in SQL.

User friendly, at first, meant something quite abstract and useful - intuitively controllable. Now it means mouse driven and GUI. I believe that both these changes can be attributed to the messages so strongly sent in the respective marketing wars which instigated them - one - Oracle, Informix and Ingres SQL battles, and - two - Microsoft's unprecedented Windows OS marketing campaign.

Now many 'experts' appear to believe in these distortions of marketing as scientific truth. I think that most people called 'expert', in any field, are those who are well-versed in Conventional Wisdom. -- Peter Lynch

A while ago we hired an engineer to suggest a drainage solution for our house. I'm glad he was well-versed in Conventional Wisdom. -- John Duncan


The arguments that favor cases where the appeal results in a correct course miss the point: as mentioned previously, argumentum ad verecundiam means "appeal to reverence". It's not the authority on the subject being appealed to, it's the respect, and it effectively dares the opponent to denigrate the revered person. It's similar to an ad hominem argument, in fact, but in a "positive" manner. An argument cannot be logically made from the force of (relevant) authority, though it's certainly a respectable rhetorical device. Appeals to reverence alone, however, are considered weak (and fallacious) rhetorical devices. Consider, one deciding funding for community health clinics located in poor areas: one run by local government, or one run by the Missionaries of Charity. While either might have their strengths, one might face extreme backlash for passing up the latter -- who are you to snub Mother Theresa? (Possibly easier now that the less-than-stellar fiscal management of her order has come to be known).


The Latin means "appeal to reverence".

Is there any way to support that statement without an argument from authority?

Excellent point. As I have noted above, arguments from authority are not generally fallacious; the claim that they are, which is the basis for this article, is itself fallacious -- an instance of the logicist fallacy. See Logical Positivism.


If anyone has a paper certificate, such as a PhD or Microsoft Certification, you better believe them. And you better not ask questions. They are right, and that is that. True with many medical doctors who prescribe medicine within 10 minutes, without really informing you of any side affects. But also true with many programmers who just "know whats best" because of their magical intuition and certificate.

Watch out for people who always speak or write in a very clear and precise manner too, with no pondering about anything. If they rarely ask or hint questions, they already know everything. Short and precise sentences with never even a hint of run-on. They know they are just right. This is dangerous. Watch out for them


A friend of mine is currently in a debate wherein his oponent is falliciously appealing to authority. This friend has come to me for help in explaining the fallacy (since his oponent does not believe he is commiting a fallacy). Here is the dialogue:

Steve: Macroevolution is true, see this article on the Stickleback as proof. [Article gives examples of mircoevolution (change within a species) amongst the stickleback population. The author, an alleged expert on evolution, argues that this proves macroevolution (the creation of a new species).]

Brett: This article gives examples of microevolution, not macroevolution. Change within a species is, by definition, microevolution. Since this article only gives examples of microevolution, it does not prove macroevolution. Change within a species (microevolution) is a necessary condition for macroevolution (the creation of a new species) but in itself microevolution is not a sufficient condition for macroevolution. Macroevolution may or may not occur, but this article does not prove it to be so. Macroevolution does not necessarily follow from microevolution, it is a non-sequiter to suppose that it does. [Note: I am not necessarily agreeing that this argument is a non-sequitor, I am just repeating Brett's argument.]

Steve: You are too religiously blinded to admit the truth. No matter how many fallacies you invoke, the truth is, every single authority agrees that macroevolution is true and that articles such as this one prove it.

There are a lot of fallacies in Steve's final statement. First, rather than answer Brett's criticism about the stickleback article he avoides the question - he never responds to the claim that mircoe does not prove macroe. Second, there is some sort of ad hominem where he attacks Brett's religious beliefs rather than the argument. Third, not every authority agrees that marcroe is the case. There are many well though of scientists that are theists (or catastrophists), or believe in intelligent design that disagree regarding macroe. But the fallacy about which I am most concerned is what I perceive to be an appeal to authority that is fallicious. Steve states that "no matter how many fallacies you invoke...every single authority agrees that macroevolution is true..." seems to be arguing as follows:

If all authorities agree with a give theory, that theory is true. All authorities agree that macroe is true (and that articles such as this one prove it). Therefore macroe is true (and this aritlce proves it)

This is a fallacy. In debate and even rigorous logic one may appeal to authority. However, the work of that authority is thereby open to examination. If the work of the authority is called into question and found to be wanting, one cannot revert back to authority in general, he must argue against the argument presented.

Forgetting for a moment which side of the evolution debate you are on, could someone please comment. How can I help Steve understand he has committed a fallacy in the way in which he is appealing to authority.

Thank you.

We on this Wiki don't have many answers when it comes to making people see their own fallacies. Keep in mind, though, that Steve's opinion may be more along the line: "Experts - people who have, by nature, studied this subject far more than you or I - have largely come to an agreement that macro-evolution is true based on the available evidence. Scientific theories must be falsifiable by nature, so unless you have evidence to falsify this theory upon which experts largely agree, I seriously doubt you'll be able to sway anyone to your side - certainly not me." Steve doesn't care that he pointed you at the wrong paper - he probably didn't understand it anyway. Keep in mind that Burden Of Proof is, in a very practical and matter-of-fact way, to be shouldered by whomever is attempting to change what is 'accepted' truth in the audience. In this case, you're probably better off not arguing with Steve because he doesn't consider himself well enough educated in the subject to present all the proper arguments and evidence: he'll just wait for you to win against the community of experts.

Copied this nice statement to You Cant Convince Me.

"Evolution and Creationism both suck." --Phl Ip

Both sides can certainly be Zealotic. Just because you are right does not mean you are not a Zealot.

There's plenty of circumstancial evidence for macro-evolution, such as leg bones in whales and snakes. Thus, you don't have to rely on authorities. There's no other model I know of to explain these, except maybe the "sloppy creator" theory in which God uses mass copy-and-paste with low QC, which most religious folks do not accept. (I expect VB coder jokes to follow.)


Completely Useless?

Some argue that authoritative evidence is completely useless. As a practical matter, I disagree. It is indeed "weak" evidence, but not useless evidence. We often don't have time or access to reinvent the experience of others in ourselves. There's only so many shoes we can walk in and hats we can wear in a lifetime. An authority that has proved useful for other issues that we have verified is generally given more weight. In fact, there are music and movie recommendation algorithms that rely on this principle. The more another person's taste tends to match yours (based on review surveys of recommendations), the more weight their opinions are given. Of course, this is aesthetic-related metrics and not "facts", so may not be fully comparable to the issues that rage in software engineering. But then again, software engineering is largely related to psychology. -top

[Referencing another's work is not an Ad Verecundiam, neither is the example you gave.]

It Depends on who the authority is. The catholic pope is an authority, and should be ignored. Ed Codd was an authority on relational, and he should be listened to.

[No, it doesn't depend on who the authority is. Stating the the pope's arguments should be ignored because he's the pope is an Ad Hominem, and stating that Ed Codd's arguments should be accepted because he's Ed Codd is an Ad Verecundiam. Both are fallacies.]



See original on c2.com